Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Mostrar: 20 | 50 | 100
Resultados 1 - 20 de 654
Filtrar
1.
Philos Ethics Humanit Med ; 19(1): 4, 2024 Apr 24.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38654305

RESUMO

Healthcare professionals often face ethical conflicts and challenges related to decision-making that have necessitated consideration of the use of conscientious objection (CO). No current guidelines exist within Spain's healthcare system regarding acceptable rationales for CO, the appropriate application of CO, or practical means to support healthcare professionals who wish to become conscientious objectors. As such, a procedural framework is needed that not only assures the appropriate use of CO by healthcare professionals but also demonstrates its ethical validity, legislative compliance through protection of moral freedoms and patients' rights to receive health care. Our proposal consists of prerequisites of eligibility for CO (individual reference, specific clinical context, ethical justification, assurance of non-discrimination, professional consistency, attitude of mutual respect, assurance of patient rights and safety) and a procedural process (notification and preparation, documentation and confidentiality, evaluation of prerequisites, non-abandonment, transparency, allowance for unforeseen objection, compensatory responsibilities, access to guidance and/or consultative advice, and organizational guarantee of professional substitution). We illustrate the real-world utility of the proposed framework through a case discussion in which our guidelines are applied.


Assuntos
Recusa Consciente em Tratar-se , Espanha , Humanos , Recusa Consciente em Tratar-se/ética , Guias como Assunto , Recusa em Tratar/ética , Recusa em Tratar/legislação & jurisprudência
4.
New Bioeth ; 27(3): 266-284, 2021 Sep.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34355660

RESUMO

Babylon 5, like other great sci-fi franchises, touched on important ethical questions. Two ethical conundrums relating to the series' main characters included providing life-saving treatment to a child against their parents' wishes and potential involvement with a highly beneficial but morally dubious medication. I use these cases to discuss some aspects of the COVID-19 vaccines' development and roll-out, demonstrating that people (be it patients or clinicians) might object to some vaccines due to reasonable ethics and safety-based concerns rather than due to an anti-vaxxer mind-set. I highlight that it would be disingenuous to lump these two groups of objections together for not all objections to specific vaccines are objections to vaccination in general. Rather, governments and pharmaceutical companies should seriously engage with the concerns of reasonable objectors to provide citizens with the appropriate products and ensure large vaccination uptake - in the case of COVID-19 this should include giving patients the choice of the product they will be inoculated with.


Assuntos
COVID-19/prevenção & controle , Consciência , Recusa em Tratar/ética , Vacinas contra COVID-19/administração & dosagem , Criança , Drama , Humanos , Princípios Morais , Segurança do Paciente
5.
Fertil Steril ; 115(2): 263-267, 2021 02.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33579519

RESUMO

Respect for patient autonomy is a critical concept in the training of all physicians. Most physicians will make clinical recommendations on a daily basis that reflect a marriage of evidence-based medical fact and the deeply felt aspirations and boundaries that patients share with them. While most physicians are well versed and comfortable managing issues of patient autonomy, many are less confident about ethical and legal guidelines for expressing their own autonomy in clinical decision-making. This paper will review the legal landscape surrounding the patient-physician relationship with a focus on when and how physicians can exercise their personal and professional autonomy in their clinical practice.


Assuntos
Relações Médico-Paciente , Médicos/legislação & jurisprudência , Autonomia Profissional , Recusa em Tratar/legislação & jurisprudência , Discriminação Social/legislação & jurisprudência , Tomada de Decisão Clínica/ética , Tomada de Decisão Clínica/métodos , Ética Médica , Humanos , Relações Médico-Paciente/ética , Médicos/ética , Recusa em Tratar/ética , Discriminação Social/ética
7.
Cuad Bioet ; 31(103): 367-375, 2020.
Artigo em Espanhol | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33375803

RESUMO

The identification, priorization and anticipation of the ethics conflicts, allow the Healthcare Ethics Committees (HEC) a better approach to them, as well as the adoption of measures to prevent its appearance and/or its mitigation. For this purpose, we set ourselves the objective of knowing what they are in the present, how important they are, and what would be the future scenario to face. An qualitative structure research was made whit two focal groups whit the participation of nurses, nurse auxiliary and doctors from the hospitalization area, they also answer a future ethics conflicts Decalogue. The results were tested after by their importance level (Relevance-Frequency-Consistency). The medium age of the participants was 34,7 +- 15,4, whit a medium experience at work of 11,7 +- 15,4 years. A total of 40 ethics conflicts was identify grouped in 5 risk areas: professional, assistance, social, organizational and legal. From there 21 results the more important, between them we find patient abandonment, inexistence of internal performance protocols, patient and relatives false expectations waiting for non-assistance care, unnecessary care at the end of the life, lack of rules for family / caregivers, and ignorance of legality. The more important ethical dilemmas for the future identified by the personal will be patients in abandonment, the lack of sociohealth resources, conflicts with family / caregivers situation and lack of information for decision making at the end of the life. The ethical conflicts between the personal from a chronic patients hospital and the relatives/caregivers was identifying, the most important were prioritized, and futures were anticipated. In these scenarios, we highlight abandonment as the most important. A map of ethics conflicts is a good tool to identify risk areas for ethics conflicts, we see the difference between the ethics conflicts found in other kind of hospitals. The map of ethics conflicts need to be update periodically to keep the validity.


Assuntos
Doença Crônica , Comitês de Ética Clínica , Hospitalização , Negociação , Adolescente , Adulto , Idoso , Dissidências e Disputas , Feminino , Grupos Focais , Hospitais Privados , Violação de Direitos Humanos/ética , Humanos , Relações Interprofissionais , Entrevistas como Assunto , Masculino , Pessoa de Meia-Idade , Relações Profissional-Família , Recusa em Tratar/ética , Fatores de Risco , Espanha , Assistência Terminal/ética , Procedimentos Desnecessários/ética , Adulto Jovem
9.
Philos Ethics Humanit Med ; 15(1): 7, 2020 09 09.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32900388

RESUMO

BACKGROUND: Normally, physicians understand they have a duty to treat patients, and they perform accordingly consistent with codes of medical practice, standards of care, and inner moral motivation. In the case of COVID-19 pandemic in a developing country such as Bangladesh, however, the fact is that some physicians decline either to report for duty or to treat patients presenting with COVID-19 symptoms. At issue ethically is whether such medical practitioners are to be automatically disciplined for dereliction of duty and gross negligence; or, on the contrary, such physicians may legitimately claim a professional right of autonomous judgment, on the basis of which professional right they may justifiably decline to treat patients. METHODS: This ethical issue is examined with a view to providing some guidance and recommendations, insofar as the conditions of medical practice in an under-resourced country such as Bangladesh are vastly different from medical practice in an industrialized nation such as the USA. The concept of moral dilemma as discussed by philosopher Michael Shaw Perry and philosopher Immanuel Kant's views on moral appeal to "emergency" are considered pertinent to sorting through the moral conundrum of medical care during pandemic. RESULTS: Our analysis allows for conditional physician discretion in the decision to treat COVID-19 patients, i.e., in the absence of personal protective equipment (PPE) combined with claim of duty to family. Physicians are nonetheless expected to provide a minimum of initial clinical assessment and stabilization of a patient before initiating transfer of a patient to a "designated" COVID-19 hospital. The latter is to be done in coordination with the national center control room that can assure admission of a patient to a referral hospital prior to ambulance transport. CONCLUSIONS: The presence of a moral dilemma (i.e., conflict of obligations) in the pandemic situation of clinical care requires institutional authorities to exercise tolerance of individual physician moral decision about the duty to care. Hospital or government authority should respond to such decisions without introducing immediate sanction, such as suspension from all clinical duties or termination of licensure, and instead arrange for alternative clinical duties consistent with routine medical care.


Assuntos
Betacoronavirus , Infecções por Coronavirus , Obrigações Morais , Pandemias , Médicos/ética , Pneumonia Viral , Recusa em Tratar/ética , Bangladesh , COVID-19 , Humanos , Autonomia Profissional , SARS-CoV-2
10.
J Bioeth Inq ; 17(4): 697-701, 2020 Dec.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32840830

RESUMO

From the ethics perspective, "duty of care" is a difficult and contested term, fraught with misconceptions and apparent misappropriations. However, it is a term that clinicians use frequently as they navigate COVID-19, somehow core to their understanding of themselves and their obligations, but with uncertainty as to how to translate or operationalize this in the context of a pandemic. This paper explores the "duty of care" from a legal perspective, distinguishes it from broader notions of duty on professional and personal levels, and proposes a working taxonomy for practitioners to better understand the concept of "duty" in their response to COVID-19.


Assuntos
COVID-19/epidemiologia , Ética Profissional , Obrigações Morais , Pandemias/ética , Papel Profissional , Beneficência , Códigos de Ética , Humanos , Recusa em Tratar/ética , Recusa em Tratar/legislação & jurisprudência , Assunção de Riscos , SARS-CoV-2 , Responsabilidade Social
11.
Pediatrics ; 146(Suppl 1): S54-S59, 2020 08.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32737233

RESUMO

In 2017, the court case over medical treatment of UK infant, Charlie Gard, reached global attention. In this article, I will analyze one of the more distinctive elements of the case. The UK courts concluded that treatment of Charlie Gard was not in his best interests and that it would be permissible to withdraw life-sustaining treatment. However, in addition, the court ruled that Charlie should not be transferred overseas for the treatment that his parents sought, even though specialists in Italy and the US were willing to provide that treatment. Is it ethical to prevent parents from pursuing life-prolonging treatment overseas for their children? If so, when is it ethical to do this? I will outline arguments in defense of obstructing transfer in some situations. I will argue, however, that this is only justified if there is good reason to think that the proposed treatment would cause harm.


Assuntos
Temas Bioéticos , Futilidade Médica/ética , Transferência de Pacientes/ética , Suspensão de Tratamento/ética , Dissidências e Disputas , História do Século XXI , Humanos , Internacionalidade , Malformações Arteriovenosas Intracranianas/terapia , Itália , Masculino , Futilidade Médica/legislação & jurisprudência , Turismo Médico/ética , Turismo Médico/legislação & jurisprudência , Pais , Transferência de Pacientes/legislação & jurisprudência , Recusa em Tratar/ética , Recusa em Tratar/legislação & jurisprudência , Texas , Traqueostomia/ética , Traqueostomia/legislação & jurisprudência , Reino Unido , Estados Unidos , Suspensão de Tratamento/legislação & jurisprudência
13.
J Clin Ethics ; 31(2): 146-153, 2020.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32585659

RESUMO

Conscientious objection in healthcare is often granted by many legislations regulating morally controversial medical procedures, such as abortion or medical assistance in dying. However, there is virtually no protection of positive claims of conscience, that is, of requests by healthcare professionals to provide certain services that they conscientiously believe ought to be provided, but that are ruled out by institutional policies. Positive claims of conscience have received comparatively little attention in academic debates. Some think that negative and positive claims of conscience deserve equal protection in terms of measures that institutions ought to take to accommodate them. However, in this issue of The Journal of Clinical Ethics (JCE), Abram Brummett argues against this symmetry thesis.1 He suggests that the relevant distinction is not between negative and positive claims of conscience, but between negative and positive rights of conscience. He argues that conscientious refusals and positive claims of conscience are both already protected as negative rights of conscience, but that this does not require institutions to accommodate positive claims of conscience. In this article I will argue that both Brummett and the authors he criticizes share a wrong view about the existence of conscience rights in healthcare. I will argue that there is no right to conscientious objection in healthcare, whether positive or negative. Thus, contra Brummett, I argue that the question whether such rights are positive or negative is as irrelevant as the question whether the claims of conscience are positive or negative.


Assuntos
Aborto Induzido , Consciência , Recusa em Tratar , Atenção à Saúde , Feminino , Pessoal de Saúde , Humanos , Masculino , Gravidez , Recusa em Tratar/ética , Recusa em Tratar/legislação & jurisprudência , Suicídio Assistido/ética
14.
Anaesth Crit Care Pain Med ; 39(3): 333-339, 2020 06.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32426441

RESUMO

BACKGROUND: Relying on capacity increases and patient transfers to deal with the huge and continuous inflow of COVID-19 critically ill patients is a strategy limited by finite human and logistical resources. RATIONALE: Prioritising both critical care initiation and continuation is paramount to save the greatest number of lives. It enables to allocate scarce resources in priority to those with the highest probability of benefiting from them. It is fully ethical provided it relies on objective and widely shared criteria, thus preventing arbitrary decisions and guaranteeing equity. Prioritisation seeks to fairly allocate treatments, maximise saved lives, gain indirect life benefits from prioritising exposed healthcare and similar workers, give priority to those most penalised as a last resort, and apply similar prioritisation schemes to all patients. PRIORITISATION STRATEGY: Prioritisation schemes and their criteria are adjusted to the level of resource scarcity: strain (level A) or saturation (level B). Prioritisation yields a four level priority for initiation or continuation of critical care: P1-high priority, P2-intermediate priority, P3-not needed, P4-not appropriate. Prioritisation schemes take into account the patient's wishes, clinical frailty, pre-existing chronic condition, along with severity and evolution of acute condition. Initial priority level must be reassessed, at least after 48h once missing decision elements are available, at the typical turning point in the disease's natural history (ICU days 7 to 10 for COVID-19), and each time resource scarcity levels change. For treatments to be withheld or withdrawn, a collegial decision-making process and information of patient and/or next of kin are paramount. PERSPECTIVE: Prioritisation strategy is bound to evolve with new knowledge and with changes within the epidemiological situation.


Assuntos
Betacoronavirus , Infecções por Coronavirus/terapia , Cuidados Críticos/organização & administração , Estado Terminal , Prioridades em Saúde/normas , Recursos em Saúde/provisão & distribuição , Unidades de Terapia Intensiva/organização & administração , Pandemias , Pneumonia Viral/terapia , Triagem/normas , COVID-19 , Canadá , Cuidadores , Continuidade da Assistência ao Paciente/organização & administração , Infecções por Coronavirus/epidemiologia , Cuidados Críticos/ética , Cuidados Críticos/normas , França/epidemiologia , Pessoal de Saúde , Prioridades em Saúde/ética , Acessibilidade aos Serviços de Saúde/ética , Humanos , Unidades de Terapia Intensiva/provisão & distribuição , Transferência de Pacientes , Pneumonia Viral/epidemiologia , Guias de Prática Clínica como Assunto , Recusa em Tratar/ética , Alocação de Recursos/ética , SARS-CoV-2 , Justiça Social , Suíça , Triagem/ética , Triagem/organização & administração
18.
AMA J Ethics ; 22(3): E209-216, 2020 03 01.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32220267

RESUMO

This article canvasses laws protecting clinicians' conscience and focuses on dilemmas that occur when a clinician refuses to perform a procedure consistent with the standard of care. In particular, the article focuses on patients' experience with a conscientiously objecting clinician at a secular institution, where patients are least likely to expect conscience-based care restrictions. After reviewing existing laws that protect clinicians' conscience, the article discusses limited legal remedies available to patients.


Assuntos
Consciência , Legislação Médica , Médicos , Recusa em Tratar , Ética Médica , Humanos , Organizações , Médicos/ética , Médicos/legislação & jurisprudência , Recusa em Tratar/ética , Recusa em Tratar/legislação & jurisprudência
19.
Early Hum Dev ; 142: 104955, 2020 03.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32006786

RESUMO

OBJECTIVE: To explore the ethical beliefs and attitudes of Argentinean neonatologists regarding limitation of life-sustaining treatment (LST) for very sick infants. METHODS: We used an anonymous questionnaire including direct questions and hypothetical clinical cases (inevitable demise and anticipated survival with severe long-term disability). Multivariable analysis was carried out to assess the relation between type of clinical case and physicians' LST attitudes. RESULTS: Overall, 315 neonatologists in 34 units in the Buenos Aires region participated (response rate 54%). Most responders would agree with decisions to start or continue LST. In both clinical cases, continuing current treatment with no therapeutic escalation was the only form of LST limitation acceptable to a substantial proportion (about 60%) of neonatologists. Agreement with LST limitation was slightly but significantly more likely when death was inevitable. CONCLUSION: Argentinean neonatologists showed a conservative attitude regarding LST limitation. Patient prognosis and options of non-treatment decision significantly influenced their choices.


Assuntos
Terapia Intensiva Neonatal/ética , Neonatologistas/psicologia , Suspensão de Tratamento/ética , Adulto , Argentina , Tomada de Decisão Clínica , Cultura , Feminino , Humanos , Recém-Nascido , Masculino , Pessoa de Meia-Idade , Recusa em Tratar/ética
20.
J Relig Health ; 59(2): 639-650, 2020 Apr.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31925633

RESUMO

Conscientious objection remains a very heated topic with strong opinions arguing for and against its utilization in contemporary health care. This paper summarizes and analyzes various arguments in the bioethical literature, favoring and opposing conscientious objection, as well as some of the proposed solutions and compromises. I then present a paradigm shifting compromise approach that arises out of very recent Jewish bioethical thought that refocuses the discussion and can minimize the frequency with which conscientious objection is required.


Assuntos
Temas Bioéticos , Consciência , Atenção à Saúde/ética , Pessoal de Saúde/psicologia , Recusa em Tratar/ética , Bioética , Dissidências e Disputas , Humanos
SELEÇÃO DE REFERÊNCIAS
DETALHE DA PESQUISA